Kant, ‘Theory and Practice’, part 2
Full title: ‘On the
common saying: this may be true in theory but it does not apply in practice’,
1793
Blue text
in square brackets ([ ]) shows the German original
Blue
pointed brackets (< >) show the English phrase to which the German
original corresponds
Notes on
the translation:
‘People’ is
usually used to translate Volk, but occasionally the translator uses
‘nation’ instead
‘Right’ is
always used to translate Recht
‘Law’ is
always used to translate Gesetz
‘Lawful’ is
always used to translate rechtlich (or some similar term)
‘Legal’ is
usually used to translate rechtlich but occasionally to translate gesetzmäßig
‘State’ is
used indiscriminately to translate Staat (i.e. a political community or its
centralised apparatus of government) and Zustand (i.e. a condition or
state of affairs, as in Naturzustand, the state of nature)
The phrase rechtliche Zustand,
which means something like ‘a state or condition of right’, in contrast with a
state of nature, is variously translated as ‘lawful state’, ‘legal state’ and
‘legal position’
II ON THE RELATIONSHIP
OF THEORY TO PRACTICE IN POLITICAL RIGHT [STAATSRECHT]
(Against Hobbes)8
Among all the
contracts by which a large group of men unites to form a society (pactum
sociale), the contract establishing a civil constitution (pactum unionis
civilis) is of an exceptional nature. For while, so far as its execution is
concerned, it has much in common with all others that are likewise directed
towards a chosen end to be pursued by joint effort, it is essentially different
from all others in the principle of its constitution (constitutionis
civilis). In all social contracts, we find a union of many individuals for
some common end which they all share. But a union as an end in itself
which they all ought to share and which is thus an absolute and primary
duty in all external relationships whatsoever among human beings (who cannot
avoid mutually influencing one another), is only found in a society in so far
as it constitutes a civil state, i.e. a commonwealth. And the end which is a
duty in itself in such external relationships, and which is indeed the highest
formal condition (conditio sine qua non) of all other external duties,
is the right of men under coercive public laws by which each can
be given what is due to him and secured against attack from any others.
But the whole concept
of an external right [Rechts] is derived
entirely from the concept of freedom in the mutual external
relationships of human beings, and has nothing to do with the end which all men
have by nature (i.e. the aim of achieving happiness) or with the recognised
means of attaining this end. And thus the latter end must on no account
interfere as a determinant with the laws governing external right. Right is
the restriction of each individual’s freedom so that it harmonises with the
freedom of everyone else (in so far as this is possible within the terms of a
general law). And public right is the distinctive quality of the external
laws which make this constant harmony possible. Since every restriction of
freedom through the arbitrary will of another party is termed coercion, it
follows that a civil constitution is a relationship among free men who are
subject to coercive laws, while they retain their freedom within the general
union with their fellows. Such is the requirement of pure reason, which
legislates a priori, regardless of all empirical ends (which can all be
summed up under the general heading of happiness). Men have different views on
the empirical end of happiness and what it consists of, so that as far as
happiness is concerned, their will cannot be brought under any [74] common
principle nor thus under any external law harmonising with the freedom of
everyone.
The civil state [bürgliche Zustand], regarded purely as a lawful
state [rechtlicher Zustand], is based on the
following a priori principles:
The freedom of
every member of society as a human being.
The equality of
each with all the others as a subject.
The independence of
each member of a commonwealth as a citizen.
These principles are
not so much laws given by an already established state [Staat],
as laws by which a state can alone be established in accordance with pure
rational principles of external human right. Thus:
1. Man’s freedom as
a human being, as a principle for the constitution of a commonwealth, can be
expressed in the following formula. No-one can compel me to be happy in
accordance with his conception of the welfare of others, for each may seek his
happiness in whatever way he sees fit, so long as he does not infringe upon the
freedom of others to pursue a similar end which can be reconciled with the
freedom of everyone else within a workable general law – i.e. he must accord to
others the same right as he enjoys himself. A government might be established
on the principle of benevolence towards the people, like that of a father
towards his children. Under such a paternal government (imperium paternale),
the subjects, as immature children who cannot distinguish what is truly
useful or harmful to themselves, would be obliged to behave purely passively
and to rely upon the judgement of the head of state as to how they ought to
be happy, and upon his kindness in willing their happiness at all. Such a
government is the greatest conceivable despotism, i.e. a constitution
which suspends the entire freedom of its subjects, who thenceforth have no
rights whatsoever. The only conceivable government for men <who are capable of possessing rights> [der Rechte fahig sind], even if the ruler is benevolent, is not a paternal
but a patriotic government (imperium non paternale, sed
patrioticum). A patriotic attitude is one where everyone in the
state, not excepting its head, regards the commonwealth as a maternal womb, or
the land as the paternal ground from which he himself sprang and which he must
leave to his descendants as a treasured pledge. Each regards himself as
authorised to protect the rights of the commonwealth by laws of the general
will, but not to submit it to his personal use at his own absolute pleasure.
This right of freedom belongs to each member of the commonwealth as a human
being, in so far as each is a being capable of possessing rights.
2. Man’s equality as
a subject might be formulated as follows. Each member of the commonwealth has
rights of coercion in relation to all the [75] others, except in relation to
the head of state. For he alone is not a member of the commonwealth, but its
creator or preserver, and he alone is authorised to coerce others without being
subject to any coercive law himself. But all who are subject to laws are the
subjects of a state, and are thus subject to the right of coercion along with
all other members of the commonwealth; the only exception is a single person
(in either the physical or the moral sense of the word), the head of state,
through whom alone the rightful coercion of all others can be exercised. For if
he too could be coerced, he would not be the head of state, and the hierarchy
of subordination would ascend infinitely. But if there were two persons exempt
from coercion, neither would be subject to coercive laws, and neither could do
to the other anything contrary to right, which is impossible.
This uniform equality
of human beings as subjects of a state is, however, perfectly consistent with
the utmost inequality of the mass in the degree of its possessions, whether
these take the form of physical or mental superiority over others, or of
fortuitous external property and of particular rights (of which there may be
many) with respect to others. Thus the welfare of the one depends very much on
the will of the other (the poor depending on the rich), the one must obey the
other (as the child its parents or the wife her husband), the one serves (the
labourer) while the other pays, etc. Nevertheless, they are all equal as
subjects before the law, which, as the pronouncement of the general
will, can only be single in form, and which concerns the form of right and not
the material or object in relation to which I possess rights. For no-one can
coerce anyone else other than through the public law and its executor, the head
of state, while everyone else can resist the others in the same way and to the
same degree. No-one, however, can lose this authority to coerce others and to
have rights towards them except through committing a crime. And no-one can
voluntarily renounce his rights by a contract or legal [rechtliche]
transaction to the effect that he has no rights but only duties, for
such a contract would deprive him of the
right to make a contract, and would thus invalidate the one he had already
made.
From this idea of the
equality of men as subjects in a commonwealth, there emerges this further
formula: every member of the commonwealth must be entitled to reach any degree
of rank which a subject can earn through his talent, his industry and his good
fortune. And his fellow subjects may not stand in his way by hereditary prerogatives
or privileges of rank and thereby hold him and his descendants back
indefinitely.
All right consists
solely in the restriction of the freedom of others, with the qualification that
their freedom can co-exist with my freedom within [76]
the terms of a general law; and public right in a commonwealth is simply a
state of affairs regulated by a real legislation which conforms to this
principle and is backed up by power, and under which a whole people live as
subjects in a lawful state [rechtlichen Zustand] (status
iuridicus). This is what we call a civil state, and it is characterised by
equality in the effects and counter-effects of freely willed actions which
limit one another in accordance with the general law of freedom. Thus the birthright
of each individual in such a state (i.e. before he has performed any acts
which can be judged in relation to right) is absolutely equal as regards
his authority to coerce others to use their freedom in a way which harmonises
with his freedom. Since birth is not an act on the part of the one who is born,
it cannot create any inequality in his legal position [rechtlichen
Zustandes] and cannot make him submit to any coercive laws except in so
far as he is a subject, along with all the others, of the one supreme
legislative power. Thus no member of the commonwealth can have a hereditary
privilege as against his fellow-subjects; and no-one can hand down to his
descendants the privileges attached to the rank he occupies in the
commonwealth, ‘nor act as if he were qualified as a ruler by birth and forcibly
prevent others from reaching the higher levels of the hierarchy (which are superior
and inferior, but never imperans and subiectus) through
their own merit. He may hand down everything else, so long as it is material
and not pertaining to his person, for it may be acquired and disposed of as
property and may over a series of generations create considerable inequalities
in wealth among the members of the commonwealth (the employee and the
employer, the landowner and the agricultural servants, etc.). But he may not
prevent his subordinates from raising themselves to his own level if they are
able and entitled to do so by their talent, industry and good fortune. If this
were not so, he would be allowed to practise coercion without himself being
subject to coercive counter-measures from others, and would thus be more than
their fellow-subject. No-one who lives within the lawful state [rechtlichen Zustande] of a commonwealth can forfeit
this equality other than through some crime of his own, but never by contract
or through military force (occupatio bellica). For no legal [rechtliche] transaction on his part or on that of
anyone else can make him cease to be his own master [Eigner
seiner selbst]. He cannot become like a domestic animal to be employed
in any chosen capacity and retained therein without consent for any desired
period, even with the reservation (which is at times sanctioned by religion, as
among the Indians) that he may not be maimed or killed. He can be considered
happy in any condition so long as he is aware that, if he does not reach the
same level as others, the fault lies either with himself (i.e. lack of ability
or serious [77] endeavour) or with circumstances for which he cannot blame
others, and not with the irresistible will of any outside party. For as far as
right is concerned, his fellow-subjects have no advantage over him.*
If we try to find a
definite meaning for the word gracious, as distinct from kind,
beneficent, protective etc., we see that it can be attributed only to a person
to whom no coercive rights apply. Thus only the head of the state’s
government, who enacts and distributes all benefits that are possible
within the public laws (for the sovereign who provides them is, as it
were, invisible, and is not an agent but the personified law itself), can be
given the title of gracious lord, for he is the only individual to whom
coercive rights do not apply. And even in an aristocratic government, as for
example in Venice, the senate is the only ‘gracious lord’. The nobles
who belong to it, even including the Doge (for only the plenary
council is the sovereign), are all subjects and equal to the others so far
as the exercise of rights is concerned, for each subject has coercive rights
towards every one of them. Princes (i.e. persons with a hereditary right to
become rulers) are themselves called gracious lords only with future reference,
an account of their claims to become rulers (i.e. by courtly etiquette, par
courtoisie). But as owners of property, they are none the less
fellow-subjects of the others, and even the humblest of their servants must possess
a right of coercion against them through the head of state. Thus there can be
no more than one gracious lord in a state. And as for gracious (more correctly distinguished)
ladies, they can be considered entitled to this appellation by their rank
and their sex (thus only as opposed to the male sex), and
this only by virtue of a refinement of manners (known as gallantry) whereby the
male sex imagines that it does itself greater honour by giving the fair sex
precedence over itself.
3. The independence
(sibisufficientia) of a member of the commonwealth as a citizen, i.e.
as a co-legislator, may be defined as follows. In the question of actual
legislation, all who are free and equal under existing public laws may be
considered equal, but not as regards the right to make these laws. Those who
are not entitled to this right are nonetheless obliged, as members of the
commonwealth, to comply with these laws, and they thus likewise enjoy their
protection (not as citizens but as co-beneficiaries of this protection).
For all right depends on laws. But a public law which defines for everyone that
which is permitted and prohibited by right, is the act of a public will, from
which all right proceeds and which must not therefore itself be able to do an
injustice [Unrecht] to any one. And this
requires no less than the will of the entire people (since all men decide for
all men and each decides for himself). For only towards oneself can one never
act unjustly [unrecht tun]. But on the other
hand, the will of another person cannot decide anything for someone without
injustice [unrecht], so that the law made by
this other person would require a further law to limit his legislation. Thus an
individual will cannot legislate for a commonwealth. For this requires freedom,
equality and unity of the will of all the members. And the
prerequisite for unity, since it necessitates a general vote (if freedom and
equality are both present), is independence. The basic law, which can come only
from the general, united <will of the people> [Volkswillen], is called the original
contract.
Anyone who has the
right to vote on this legislation is a citizen (citoyen, [78]
i.e. citizen of a state, not bourgeois or citizen of a town). The only
qualification required by a citizen (apart, of course, from being an adult
male) is that he must be his own master [sein
eigener Herr] (sui iuris), and must have some property (which
can include any skill, trade, fine art or science) to support himself. In cases
where he must earn his living from others, he must earn it only by selling that
which is his,* and not by allowing others to make use of him; for he must in
the true sense of the word serve no-one but the commonwealth. In this
respect, artisans and large or small landowners are all equal, and each is
entitled to one vote only. As for landowners, we leave aside the question of
how anyone can have rightfully acquired more land than he can cultivate with
his own hands (for acquisition by military seizure is not primary acquisition),
and how it came about that numerous people who might otherwise have acquired
permanent property were thereby reduced to serving someone else in order to
live at all. It would certainly conflict with the above principle of equality
if a law were to grant them a privileged status so that their descendants would
always remain feudal landowners, without their land being sold or divided by
inheritance and thus made useful to more people; it would also be unjust if
only those belonging to an arbitrarily selected class were allowed to acquire
land, should the estates in fact be divided. The owner of a large estate keeps
out as many smaller property owners (and their votes) as could otherwise occupy
his territories. He does not vote on their behalf, and himself has only one vote.
It should be left exclusively to the ability, industry and good fortune of each
member of the commonwealth to enable each to acquire a part and all to acquire
the whole, although this distinction cannot be observed within the general
legislation itself. The number of those entitled to vote on matters of
legislation must be calculated purely from the number of property owners, not
from the size of their properties.
He who does a piece of
work (opus) can sell it to someone else, just as if it were his own
property. But guaranteeing one’s labour (praestatio operae) is not the
same as selling a commodity. The domestic servant, the shop assistant, the
labourer, or even the barber, are merely labourers (operarii), not artists
(artifices, in the wider sense) or members of the state, and are thus
unqualified to be citizens. And although the man to whom I give my firewood to
chop and the tailor to whom I give material to make into clothes both appear to
have a similar relationship towards me, the former differs from the latter in
the same way as the barber from the wig-maker (to whom I may in fact have given
the requisite hair) or the labourer from the artist or tradesman, who does a
piece of work which belongs to him until he is paid for it. For the latter, in
pursuing his trade, exchanges his property with someone else (opus), while
the former allows someone else to make use of him. – But I do admit that it is
somewhat difficult to define the qualifications which entitle anyone to claim
the status of being his own master.
Those who possess this
right to vote must agree unanimously to the law of public justice [Gerechtigkeit], or else a legal contention [Rechtstreit] would arise between those who [79]
agree and those who disagree, and it would require yet another higher legal
principle [Rechtsprinzips] to resolve it. An
entire people cannot, however, be expected to reach unanimity, but only to show
a majority of votes (and not even of direct votes, but simply of the votes of
those delegated in a large nation [Volke] to
represent the people [Volks]). Thus the actual
principle of being content with majority decisions must be accepted unanimously
and embodied in a contract; and this itself must be the ultimate basis on which
a civil constitution is established.
Conclusion
This, then, is an original
contract by means of which a civil and thus completely
lawful [rechtliche] constitution and
commonwealth can alone be established. But we need by no means assume that this
contract (contractus originarius or pactum sociale), based on a
coalition of the wills of all private individuals in a nation [Volk] to form a common, public will for the purposes
of rightful legislation, actually exists as a fact, for it cannot possibly
be so. Such an assumption would mean that we would first have to prove from
history that some nation [Volk], whose rights
and obligations have been passed down to us, did in fact perform such an act,
and handed down some authentic record or legal instrument, orally or in
writing, before we could regard ourselves as bound by a pre-existing civil
constitution. It is in fact merely an idea of reason, which nonetheless
has undoubted practical reality; for it can oblige every legislator to frame
his laws in such a way that they could have been produced by the united will of
a whole nation [Volks], and to regard each
subject, in so far as he can claim citizenship, as if he had consented within
the general will. This is the test of the rightfulness [Rechtmäßigkeit]
of every public law. For if the law is such that a whole people could
not possibly agree to it (for example, if it stated that a certain class
of subjects must be privileged as a hereditary ruling class), it
is unjust [nicht gerecht]; but if it is at
least possible that a people could agree
to it, it is our duty to consider the law as just [gerecht],
even if the people is at present in such a position or attitude of mind that it
would probably refuse its consent if it were consulted.*
If, for example, a war
tax were proportionately imposed on all subjects, they could not claim, simply
because it is oppressive, that it is unjust because the war is in their opinion
unnecessary. For they are not entitled to judge this issue, since it is at
least possible that the war is inevitable and the tax indispensable, so
that the tax must be deemed rightful in the judgement of the subjects. But if
certain estate owners were oppressed with levies for such a war, while others
of the same class were exempted, it is easily seen that a whole people could
never agree to a law of this kind, and it is entitled at least to make
representations against it, since an unequal distribution of burdens can never
be considered just.
But this restriction
obviously applies only to the judgement of the legislator, [80] not to that of
the subject. Thus if a people, under some existing legislation, were asked to
make a judgement which in all probability would prejudice its happiness, what
should it do? Should the people not oppose the measure? The only possible
answer is that they can do nothing but obey. For we are not concerned here with
any happiness which the subject might expect to derive from the institutions or
administration of the commonwealth, but primarily with the rights which would
thereby be secured for everyone. And this is the highest principle from which
all maxims relating to the commonwealth must begin, and which cannot be
qualified by any other principles. No generally valid principle of legislation
can be based on happiness. For both the current circumstances and the highly
conflicting and variable illusions as to what happiness is (and no-one can
prescribe to others how they should attain it) make all fixed principles
impossible, so that happiness alone can never be a suitable principle of
legislation. The doctrine that salus publica suprema civitatis lex est9
retains its value and authority undiminished; but the public welfare which
demands first consideration lies precisely in that legal [gesetzliche] constitution which guarantees everyone
his freedom within the law [durch Gesetze], so
that each remains free to seek his happiness in whatever way he thinks best, so
long as he does not violate the lawful [gesetzmäßigen]
freedom and rights of his fellow subjects at large.
If the supreme power
makes laws which are primarily directed towards happiness (the affluence of the
citizens, increased population etc.), this cannot be regarded as the end for
which a civil constitution was established, but only as a means of securing
the rightful state [rechtlichen Zustand], especially
against external enemies of the people. The head of state must be authorised to
judge for himself whether such measures are necessary for the commonwealth’s
prosperity, which is required to maintain its strength and stability both
internally and against external enemies. The aim is not, as it were, to make
the people [Volk] happy against its will, but
only to ensure its continued existence as a commonwealth.* The legislator may
indeed err in judging whether or not the measures he adopts are prudent, but
not in deciding whether or not the law harmonises with the principle of right.
For he has ready to hand as an infallible a priori standard the idea of
an original contract, and he need not wait for experience to show whether the
means are suitable, as would be necessary if they were based on the principle
of happiness. For so long as it is not self-contradictory [81] to say that an
entire people could agree to such a law, however painful it might seem, then
the law is <in harmony with right> [dem Rechte gemäß].
But if a public law is beyond reproach (i.e. irreprehensible) with
respect to right, it carries with it the authority to coerce those to whom it
applies, and conversely, it forbids them to resist the will of the legislator
by violent means. In other words, the power of the state [Staate] to put the law into effect is also irresistible,
and no rightfully established commonwealth can exist without a force of
this kind to suppress all internal resistance. For such resistance would be
dictated by a maxim which, if it became general, would destroy the whole civil
constitution and put an end to the only state [Zustand]
in which men can possess rights.
Measures of this kind
might include certain restrictions on imports, so that the means of livelihood
may be developed for the benefit of the subjects themselves and not as an
advantage to foreigners or an encouragement for their industry. For without the
prosperity of the people [Volk], the state
would not have enough strength to resist external enemies or to preserve itself
as a commonwealth.
It thus follows that
all resistance against the supreme legislative power, all incitement of the
subjects to violent expressions of discontent, all defiance which breaks out
into rebellion, is the greatest and most punishable crime in a commonwealth,
for it destroys its very foundations. This prohibition is absolute. And
even if the power of the state or its agent, the head of state, has violated
the original contract by authorising the government
to act tyrannically, and has thereby, in the eyes of the subject, forfeited the right to legislate, the subject is
still not entitled to offer counter-resistance. The reason for this is that the
people, under an existing civil constitution, has no longer any right to judge
how the constitution should be administered. For if
we suppose that it does have this right to judge and that it disagrees with the
judgement of the actual head of state, who is to decide which side is right?
Neither can act as judge of his own cause. Thus there would have to be another
head above the head of state to mediate between the latter and the people,
which is self-contradictory. – Nor can a right of necessity (ius in casu
necessitatis) be invoked here as a means of removing the barriers which
restrict the power of the people; for it is monstrous to suppose that we can
have a right to do wrong in the direst (physical) distress.* For the head of
state can just as readily claim [82] that his severe treatment of his subjects
is justified by their insubordination as the subjects can justify their
rebellion by complaints about their un-merited suffering, and who is to decide?
The decision must rest with whoever controls the ultimate enforcement of the public
law, i.e. the head of state himself. Thus no-one in the commonwealth can have a
right to contest his authority.
There is no casus
necessitatis except where duties, i.e. an absolute duty and another
which, however pressing, is nevertheless relative, come into conflict.
For instance, it might be necessary for someone to betray someone else, even if
their relationship were that of father and son, in order to preserve the state
from catastrophe. This preservation of the state from evil is an absolute duty,
while the preservation of the individual is merely a relative duty (i.e. it
applies only if he is not guilty of a crime against the state). The first
person might denounce the second to the authorities with the utmost unwillingness,
compelled only by (moral) necessity. But if a person, in order to preserve his
own life, pushes a shipwrecked fellow away from the plank he grasps, it would
be quite false to say that (physical) necessity gives him a right to do so. For
it is only a relative duty for me to preserve my own life (i.e. it applies only
if I can do so without committing a crime). But it is an absolute duty not to
take the life of another person who has not offended me and does not even make
me risk my own life. Yet the teachers of general civil law are perfectly
consistent in authorising such measures in cases of distress. For the
authorities cannot combine a penalty with this prohibition, since this
penalty would have to be death. But it would be a nonsensical law which
threatened anyone with death if he did not voluntarily deliver himself up to
death when in dangerous circumstances.
Nonetheless, estimable
men have declared that the subject is justified, under certain circumstances,
in using force against his superiors. I need name only Achenwall,10
who is extremely cautious, precise and restrained in his theories of natural
right.* He says: ‘If the danger which threatens the commonwealth as a result of
long endurance of injustices from the head of state is greater than the danger
to be feared from taking up arms against him, the people may then resist him.
It may use this right to abrogate its contract of subjection and to dethrone
him as a tyrant.’ And he concludes: ‘The people, in dethroning its ruler, thus
returns to the state of nature.’
Ius Naturae. Editio V.
Pars posterior, §§ 203–206.
I well believe that
neither Achenwall nor any others of the worthy men who have speculated along
the same lines as he would ever have given their advice or agreement to such hazardous
projects if the case had arisen. And it can scarcely be doubted that if the
revolutions whereby Switzerland, the United Netherlands or even Great Britain
won their much admired constitutions had failed, the readers of their history
would regard the execution of their celebrated founders as no more than the
deserved punishment of great political criminals. For the result usually
affects our judgement of the rightfulness of an action, although the result is
uncertain, whereas the <principles of right> [Rechtsgründe] are
constant. But it is clear that these peoples have done the greatest degree of
wrong in seeking their rights [ihr Recht] in
this way, even if we admit that such a revolution did no injustice [Unrecht] to a ruler who had violated a specific
basic agreement with the people, such as the Joyeuse Entrée.11
For such procedures, if made into a maxim, make all lawful [rechtliche] constitutions insecure and produce a
state of complete lawlessness [Gesetzlösigkeit] (status naturalis) where all rights [alles Recht] cease at least to be effectual. In view
of this tendency of so many right-thinking authors to plead on behalf of the
people (and to its own detriment), I will only remark that such errors arise in
part from the usual fallacy of allowing the principle of happiness [83] to
influence the judgement, wherever the principle of right is involved; and
partly because these writers have assumed that the idea of an original contract
(a basic postulate of reason) is something which must have taken place in
reality, even where there is no document to show that any contract was
actually submitted to the commonwealth, accepted by the head of state, and
sanctioned by both parties. Such writers thus believe that the people retains
the right to abrogate the original contract at its own discretion, if, in the
opinion of the people, the contract has been severely violated.*
Even if an actual
contract of the people with the head of state has been violated, the people
cannot reply immediately as a commonwealth, but only by forming
factions. For the hitherto existing constitution has been destroyed by the
people, but a new common wealth has still to be organised. At this point, the
state of anarchy supervenes, with all the terrors it may bring with it. And the
wrong which is thereby done is done by each faction of the people to the
others, as is clear from the case where the rebellious subjects ended up by
trying to thrust upon each other a constitution which would have been far more
oppressive than the one they abandoned. For they would have been devoured by
ecclesiastics and aristocrats, instead of enjoying greater equality in the
distribution of political burdens under a single head of state who ruled them
all.12
It is obvious from
this that the principle of happiness (which is not in fact a definite principle
at all) has ill effects in political right [Staatsrecht]
just as in morality, however good the intentions of those who teach it.
The sovereign wants to make the people [Volk]
happy as he thinks best, and thus becomes a despot, while the people [Volk] are unwilling to give up their universal
human desire to seek happiness in their own way, and thus become rebels. If
they had first of all asked what is lawful [Rechtens] (in
terms of a priori certainty, which no empiricist can upset), the idea of
a social contract would retain its authority undiminished. But it would not
exist as a fact (as Danton13 would have it, declaring that since it
does not actually exist, all property and all rights under the existing civil
constitution are null and void), but only as a rational principle for judging
any lawful [rechtlichen] public constitution
whatsoever. And it would then be seen that, until the general will is there [da ist], the people has no coercive right against its
ruler, since it can apply coercion legally [rechtlich]
only through him. But if the will is there [ist
da], no force can be applied to the ruler by the people, otherwise the
people would be the supreme ruler. Thus the people can never possess a right of
coercion against the head of state, or be entitled to oppose him in word or
deed.
We can see,
furthermore, that this theory is adequately confirmed in practice. In the
British constitution, of which the people are so proud that they hold it up as
a model for the whole world, we find no mention of what the people are entitled
to do if the monarch were to violate the contract of 1688.14 Since
there is no law to cover such a case, the people [84] tacitly reserve the right
to rebel against him if he should violate the contract. And it would be an
obvious contradiction if the constitution included a law for such
eventualities, entitling the people to overthrow the existing constitution,
from which all particular laws are derived, if the contract were violated. For
there would then have to be a publicly constituted* opposing power,
hence a second head of state to protect the rights of the people against the
first ruler, and then yet a third to decide which of the other two had right on
his side. In fact, the leaders (or guardians – call them what you will) of the
British people, fearing some such accusation if their plans did not succeed, invented
the notion of a voluntary abdication by the monarch they forced out, rather
than claim a right to depose him (which would have made the constitution
self-contradictory).
While I trust that
no-one will accuse me of flattering monarchs too much by declaring them
inviolable, I likewise hope that I shall be spared the reproach of claiming too
much for the people if I maintain that the people too have inalienable [unverlierbaren] rights against the head of state,
even if these cannot be rights of coercion.
Hobbes is of the
opposite opinion. According to him (De Cive, Chap. 7, § 14), the head of
state has no contractual obligations towards the people; he can do no injustice
[Unrecht] to a citizen, but may act towards him
as he pleases. This proposition would be perfectly correct if injustice [Unrecht] were taken to mean any injury which gave
the injured party a coercive right against the one who has done him
injustice. But in its general form, the proposition is quite terrifying.
The non-resisting
subject must be able to assume that his ruler has no wish to do him
injustice [Unrecht]. And everyone has his
inalienable rights, which he cannot give up even if he wishes to, and about
which he is entitled to make his own judgements. But if he assumes that the
ruler’s attitude is one of good will, any injustice which he believes he has
suffered can only have resulted through error, or through ignorance of certain
possible consequences of the laws which the supreme authority has made. Thus
the citizen must, with the approval of the ruler, be entitled to make public
his opinion on whatever of the ruler’s measures seem to him to constitute an
injustice against the commonwealth. For to assume that the head of state can
neither make mistakes nor be ignorant of anything would be to imply that he
receives divine inspiration and is more than a human being.
No right in a state
can be tacitly and treacherously included by a secret reservation, and least of
all a right which the people claim to be part of the constitution, for all laws
within it must be thought of as arising out of a public will. Thus if the
constitution allowed rebellion, it would have to declare this right publicly
and make clear how it might be implemented. [85] Thus freedom of the pen is
the only safeguard of the rights of the people, although it must not transcend
the bounds of respect and devotion to wards the existing constitution, which
should itself create a liberal attitude of mind among the subjects. To try to
deny the citizen this freedom does not only mean, as Hobbes maintains, that the
subject can claim no rights against the supreme ruler. It also means
withholding from the ruler all knowledge of those matters which, if he knew
about them, he would himself rectify, so that he is thereby put into a
self-stultifying position. For his will issues commands to his subjects (as
citizens) only in so far as he represents the general will of the people. But
to encourage the head of state to fear that independent and public thought
might cause political unrest is tantamount to making him distrust his own power
and feel hatred towards his people.
The general principle,
however, according to which a people may judge negatively whatever it believes
was not decreed in good will by the supreme legislation, can be summed
up as follows: Whatever a people cannot impose upon itself cannot be imposed
upon it by the legislator either.
For example, if we
wish to discover whether a law which declares permanently valid an
ecclesiastical constitution (itself formulated at some time in the past) can be
regarded as emanating from the actual will or intention of the legislator, we
must first ask whether a people is authorised [dürfe]
to make a law for itself whereby certain accepted doctrines and
outward forms of religion are declared permanent, and whether the people may
thus prevent its own descendants from making further progress in religious understanding
or from correcting any past mistakes. It is clear that any original contract of
the people which established such a law would in itself be null and void, for
it would conflict with the appointed aim and purpose [Bestimmung
und Zwecke] of mankind. Thus a law of this kind cannot be regarded as
the actual will of the monarch, to whom counter-representations may accordingly
be made. In all cases, however, where the supreme legislation did nevertheless
adopt such measures, it would be permissible to pass general and public
judgements upon them, but never to offer any verbal or active resistance.
In every commonwealth,
there must be obedience to generally valid coercive laws within the
mechanism of the political constitution. There must also be a spirit of
freedom, for in all matters concerning universal human duties, each
individual requires to be convinced by reason that the coercion which prevails
is lawful [rechtmäßig], otherwise he would be
in contradiction with himself. Obedience without the spirit of freedom is the
effective cause of all secret societies. For it is a natural vocation [Naturberuf] of man to communicate [86] with his
fellows, especially in matters affecting mankind as a whole. Thus secret
societies would disappear if freedom of this kind were encouraged. And how else
can the government itself acquire the knowledge it needs to further its own
basic intention, if not by allowing the spirit of freedom, so admirable in its
origins and effects, to make itself heard?
***
Nowhere does practice
so readily bypass all pure principles of reason and treat theory so
presumptuously as in the question of what is needed for a good political
constitution. The reason for this is that a legal [gesetzliche]
constitution of long standing gradually makes the people accustomed to
judging both their happiness and their rights in terms of the peaceful status
quo. Conversely, it does not encourage them to value the existing state of
affairs in the light of those concepts of happiness and right which reason
provides. It rather makes them prefer this passive state [Zustand] to the dangerous task of looking for a
better one, thus bearing out the saying which Hippocrates told physicians to
remember: iudicium anceps, experimentum periculosum.15 Thus
all constitutions which have lasted for a sufficiently long time, what ever
their inadequacies and variations, produce the same result: the people remain
content with what they have. If we therefore consider the welfare of the
people, theory is not in fact valid, for everything depends upon practice
derived from experience.
But reason provides a
concept which we express by the words political right [Staatsrecht]. And this concept has binding force
for human beings who coexist in a state of antagonism produced by their natural
freedom, so that it has an objective, practical reality, irrespective of the
good or ill it may produce (for these can only be known by experience). Thus it
is based on a priori principles, for experience cannot provide knowledge
of what is right, and there is a theory of political right to which
practice must conform before it can be valid.
The only objection
which can be raised against this is that, although men have in their minds the idea
of the rights to which they are entitled, their intractability is such that
they are incapable and unworthy of being treated as their rights demand, so
that they can and ought to be kept under control by a supreme power acting
purely from expediency. But this counsel of desperation (salto mortale) means
that, since there is no appeal to right but only to force, the people may
themselves resort to force and thus make every legal [gesetzliche]
constitution insecure. If there is nothing which commands immediate
respect through reason, such as <the basic
rights of man> [Das Menschenrecht], no
influence can prevail upon man’s arbitrary will and restrain his [87] freedom.
But if both benevolence and right speak out in loud tones, human nature will
not prove too debased to listen to their voice with respect. Tum pietate
gravem meritisque si forte virum quern Conspexere, silent arrectisque auribus
adstant (Virgil).16
Notes
8 p. 73. Kant seeks here to refute Hobbes’
political theory, which found its classic expression in the Leviathan (1651).
The actual argument is explicitly directed against Hobbes’ De cive (1642).
9 p. 8o. ‘The public welfare is the supreme law
of the state.’
10 p. 82. Gottfried Achenwall (1719–72),
professor in Gottingen and the leading statistician of the age. His Jus
naturae in usum auditorum was published in Gottingen, 1755–6 (7th ed.
1781). Kant used this work as a text-book for his lectures on Natural Law, held
twelve times between 1767 and 1788. The use of textbooks for lectures was customary.
11 p. 82. Charter granted to Brabant by Duke John
III in 1354 in which the Duke undertook to maintain the integrity of the duchy
and not to wage war, make treaties or impose taxes without consulting his
subjects represented by the municipalities.
12 p. 83. These remarks refer to the French
Revolution.
13 p. 83. Georges Jacques Danton (1759–94.), the
French revolutionary leader.
14 p. 83. This remark refers to the accession of
William III of Orange and Mary to the British throne in 1688 (the Glorious
Revolution). After James II had been overthrown, Parliament legislated for
William’s and Mary’s accession, restricting the monarchy to the Protestant
successors of James I.
15 p. 86. ‘The judgement is uncertain, and
experiments are dangerous.’
16 p. 87. ‘If they catch sight of a man respected
for his virtue and services, they are silent and stand close with ears alert.’
Virgil, Aeneid I, 151–2.
(Source:
H. Reiss ed. Kant’s Political Writings, ed. H. Reiss, translated by H.B.
Nisbet , Cambridge University Press 1970, pp. 73-87)
© Cambridge University Press 1970
Interpolations:
Andrew Chitty