Social and Political Philosophy
Spring-Summer 2004
Lecture 10: Rawls and social justice
1. Social justice
Ordinarily when we talk about justice we have in
mind legal justice, i.e. punishing the criminal but not the innocent, punishing
people who have committed the same crime in the same way, punishing more
serious crimes proportionately more heavily etc. A classical definition of
justice that summarises this is ‘giving people their due’. Social justice (or
distributive justice) is really an extension of the idea of a fair allocation
of punishments in the legal system to a fair allocation of goods (especially of
money) in society as a whole. Rawls summarises this idea when he says that
concept of ‘justice’ (and social justice is what he has in mind) is that of ‘a
proper distribution of the benefits and burdens of social cooperation’.
2. Hypothetical contract,
the original position and the veil of ignorance (TJ secs. 1-4)
Through
most of the 20th century normative political philosophy was dominated by
utilitarianism. Rawls resurrects contract theory as a basis for evaluating
states: more accurately, for evaluating the ‘basic structure of society’, i.e.
its economic as well as legal and political structure, from the point of view
of its ‘justice’. (He does mention that one might evaluate a social structure
from other points of view, but he clearly thinks that the point of view of
justice is the crucial one.)
He
asks us to imagine ourselves as contracting to form a social structure from an
‘original position’ (original position). Here we are behind a ‘veil of
ignorance’, i.e. none of us knows what role he or she we will end up by
occupying in the social structure. In fact no-one knows anything about
him/herself which will enable him to predict what role he/she will end up by
occupying: a person’s skin colour, sex, abilities, industriousness, physical
healthiness and so on are all behind the veil of ignorance. Also, they do not
know their own ‘conception of the good’, i.e. they do not know what they think
is ultimately valuable and worth pursuing in life.
A
social structure is more ‘just’ than another one, according to Rawls, if in the
original position people would form a contract to establish and inhabit that
social structure rather than the other. This is the essence of his theory of
justice, which he dubs ‘justice as fairness’ (with the implication that other
theories of justice do not make it a matter of fairness). In fact the idea of
forming a contract is a bit misleading, since according to Rawls anyone rational
placed in the original position, as he defines it, will have the same
preferences as between possible social structures.
3. The primary goods and the
principles of justice (TJ secs. 11, 13-15)
Behind
the veil of ignorance people do not know their own ‘conception of the good’, so
Rawls argues that they must evaluate basic social structures in terms of what
those social structures would provide them by way of goods that will be useful
to them as means towards realising their particular conception of the good no
matter what it may turn out to be. He argues that his ‘primary goods’ (rights,
liberties, opportunities, powers, income, wealth, sense of one’s own worth) are
such all-purpose means. So rather than simply assert that the good for humans
consists in their self-realisation or in excelling at human activities like art
(as perfectionists do), and rather than saying that the good for human beings
consists in happiness or preference satisfaction (as utilitarians do), he
develops a third theory of the good as consisting in those resources which will
enable you to realise any individual’s conception of the good, whatever it may
be. He calls this the ‘thin theory of the good’. It is close to a utilitarian
theory of the good though it focuses on resources rather than outcomes.
The
idea is now that people in the original position will choose between different
social structures on the basis of what quantity of primary goods they can
expect to get, in each of the different social structures in question, when
they step out from behind the veil of ignorance. The theory enables him to say
that for him ‘the right’ (i.e. principles of social justice and of individual
morality – though in later writings he drops his original ambition to extend
his theory to individual morality) is prior to ‘the good’. Justice is defined
independently of any particular conception of the good.
The
original position could be used directly to generate judgments about whether
one social structure is more just than another (e.g. Britain today with or
without a particular law). But Rawls uses it to generate general principles
which in turn can be used to generate such individual judgements. These are the
‘principles of justice’. They stipulate how primary goods must be distributed
in an ideally just social structure:
(1)
Principle of equal liberty: Give each person an equal right to the most
extensive total system of the ‘basic liberties’ (freedom of speech, assembly,
right to vote, run for elections etc.) compatible with an equal system for all.
This is an updated version of Kant’s ‘principle of right’.
(2)
Distribute economic and social advantages (income, wealth, status) so that they
are: (2a) attached to positions which are open to all under fair equality of
opportunity (‘fair equality of opportunity principle’) and (2b) to the greatest
advantage of the least advantaged (the ‘difference principle’)
The
principles are meant to be applied ‘lexicographically’, i.e. in ranking a
number of different social structures according to how just they are we should
first rank them by how well they satisfy principle (1), then break any ties by
seeing how well they satisfy principle 2(a) then break any remaining ties by
seeing how well they satisfy principle 2(b). This is like ordering words in a
dictionary.
Some
comments:
(a) The
difference principle ranks one social structure as more just than another if
the people occupying the worst-off role in that social structure are better off
than the people occupying the worst-off role in the other social structure.
Prima facie this suggests that more egalitarian societies are more just. But if
it is the case that e.g. instituting free-market capitalism will make everyone
better off than instituting a pure communism (because of the incentives to get
rich etc.) then this system will count as more just. So the difference problem
avoids the ‘levelling down’ problem faced by straightforward egalitarianism: it
has to advocate the impoverishment of everyone if that is what is needed to
bring about economic equality.
(b)
The principles of justice have a moral character to them in that they demand
either that everyone be equally well off (in terms of the basic liberties) or
that the worst off be as well off as possible (in terms of other benefits), but
this is not a result of any moral instincts on the part of the contractors, who
are assumed to act purely on self-interest. The veil of ignorance does the job
of translating self-interested decisions into principles that have a moral
character, because from behind it I have to think of how everyone will do in a
given social structure, since I might turn out to be anyone.
4. Would people in the
original position choose the principles of justice? (TJ secs. 25-26)
Rawls
assumes that the parties in the original position will adopt a ‘maximin’ or
‘disaster avoidance’ form of rationality, i.e. if they have to choose between
several options in each of which there are various different chances of
different outcomes for them, they will not choose the option under which the
average utility of those outcomes (weighted by the chance of each) is highest,
but the option for which the worst outcome is better than for any other option.
However it has been argued that a rational self-interested person would not
adopt a maximin policy (Harsanyi). For example, every time we take a plane trip
we flout the maximin principle.
5. Justifying the principles
of justice (TJ secs. 4, 20, 24)
Rawls
might respond to Harsanyi that the original position is an artificial construct
and he is entitled to define the kind of rationality the parties in it use, as
well as features like what is behind the veil of ignorance, so as to best serve
the theory. This raises the question of what justifies the principles
that would be chosen in the original position as he constructs it. He gives
several answers in sec. 4 of A Theory of
Justice:
(a)
The principles that would be chosen produce judgements about which social
structures are more/less just which correspond to our strongest intuitive moral
judgements about the relative justice of pairs of different societies in
individual cases. Here he allows for a process of ‘reflective equilibrium’
between original position and our intuitive judgements whereby we can tinker
with the definition of the original position to make it generate principles
whose rankings of social structures correspond to our strongest intuitive
judgements, while being willing to sacrifice weaker intuitive judgments for the
sake of a match between intuitive judgements and what is generated by an
original position. This is a ‘coherentist’ justification of the principles.
But
Rawls also says they would be chosen in an original position that is
‘philosophically favoured’. Here he seems to have in mind either:
(b)
The original position expresses some abstract intuitions that we have about
justice (e.g. the intuition that an argument for a principle of justice should
not be based on people’s colour is modelled by placing colour behind the veil
of ignorance in the original position).
(c)
Some even more abstract intuitions we have about the
nature of persons as free and equal which he associates with Kant (TJ sec. 40)
but is also associated with the French Revolution and can be traced back to
Rousseau and Locke. The original position is supposed to implement the idea of free and equal persons: free perhaps
because people do not know their own conception of the good (expressing the
idea that this is something it is up to each individual to choose; Mulhall and
Swift) (NB here the idea of freedom looks like that of self-authority
which I have mentioned before), and equal because
people do not know what their own skin colour, sex, abilities etc. are so they
are ‘blind’ to those things (like the figure on the Old Bailey). Freedom and
equality in turn come out in the first and second principles of justice
respectively. So the original position would be a way of ‘modelling’ the
basic idea of persons as free and equal.
(d)
He also implies that principles chosen in the original position are justified
because they are ‘justifiable to individual members of society’. But this begs
the question of what form the justification is meant to take. If it is an
argument to the effect that ‘If you were behind the veil of ignorance, you
would choose these principles too’, the obvious response is ‘Maybe, but I am
not behind the veil of ignorance, so what is it to me as I am now that if I was
then I would choose them?’ Maybe the idea is that they can be justified from an
idea of ourselves as free and equal which we all share, but this reduces to
(c). Or maybe the idea is that they can be justified from some principles which
are intrinsic to the bare idea of justification (O’Neill ‘Constructivism in
Rawls and Kant’ attributes this line of thought to Kant, though not to Rawls.)
6. Some criticisms
(a)
One criticism is that Rawls mixes up four different kinds of justification for
his original position, where he should have stuck to one. In later writings he
tends to emphasise (c) above.
(b)
Another criticism is that the concept of persons as free and equal appealed to
in (c) is an untenable metaphysical postulate (Sandel). In later writings,
Rawls responds to this by saying that the original position simply implements a
conception of the person that we in modern Western societies share (on which we
all have an ‘overlapping consensus’ despite our different religious and moral
beliefs), rather than one which is absolutely true. The implication is that his
theory is only applicable to such societies. This looks like a major concession
to ‘communitarianism’, the view that the only basis on which political
structures for a given society can be justified is the shared cultural values
of that society. (See O’Neill, ‘Constructivism in Rawls and Kant’ for a
critique of this position from a cosmopolitan-Kantian perspective). Also, does
it make the whole theory practically useless, since it presupposes that we all
agree to start with? Rawls would say no: there are deep agreements about the
freedom and equality of persons which
are shared across the political spectrum in the West, and he can show that his
principles of justice follow from those deep agreements. But to make this work
he has to show not just that his theory gives one possible interpretation of
freedom and equality of persons, but that it gives the only possible one.
(c)
The list of primary goods is skewed towards individualism. A deeply unequal
society (such as may be justified by Rawls) cuts people off from each other,
and is worse for human beings than a more equal one. Maybe this could be
rectified by adding another primary good, ‘sociability’, but this looks at odds
with the thin theory of the good as the means of generating primary goods. (See
Kymlicka)
(d)
The very way the principles are chosen on the basis of self-interest reflects
an underlying individualism. Rawls might say this is correct and implements the
idea of persons as free. (See Nagel)
(e)
Rawls says nothing about desert, but most people intuitively feel that
achievements deserve some kind of reward. (See Rogers 2002)
Supplementary readings:
Rawls, J. (1985) ‘Justice as
fairness: political not metaphysical’, Philosophy
and Public Affairs 14, reprinted in Rawls’s Collected Papers and
revised as lecture 1 secs. 1-5 of his Political
Liberalism
Rawls, J. (2001) Justice as
Fairness: A Restatement
Rogers, B. (2002) ‘Just
deserts’, Guardian 19 April 2002
(http://www.guardian.co.uk/analysis/story/0,3604,686917,00.html)
Seminar questions:
(NB section 4 of A Theory of Justice is crucial. It
should be read several times.)
1. What is the difference
between the concept of justice and a conception of justice? (TJ sec. 1)
2. Rawls claims that
principles chosen in the original position can be publicly accepted. Why should
this be? (sec. 3)
3. How can Rawls define the
original position both in ‘the most
philosophically favoured way’ and so
that it is in reflective equilibrium with our intuitive judgements about
individual cases? (secs. 4, 20)
4. What is the difference
between pure and perfect procedural justice, and why does it matter for Rawls?
(sec. 14)
5. How does Rawls justify
his ‘formal constraints on the concept of right’? (sec. 23)
6.
How does the original position ‘model’ the idea that persons are free and
equal? (sec. 40)
AC 9.3.04